Is Every Real Number The Limit Of A Sequence Of Irrational Numbers, Constructively?

by ADMIN 84 views

Introduction

In the realm of real analysis, the concept of sequences and limits plays a crucial role in understanding the properties of real numbers. A fundamental question that arises in this context is whether every real number can be expressed as the limit of a sequence of irrational numbers. This question has been extensively studied in the context of classical mathematics, where the law of the excluded middle and the axiom of choice are often employed. However, in constructive mathematics, which eschews the use of these principles, the situation is more nuanced.

Background

In constructive mathematics, the real numbers are typically defined as Dedekind cuts, which are subsets of the rational numbers that satisfy certain properties. A Dedekind cut is a partition of the rational numbers into two non-empty sets, the left set and the right set, such that every element of the left set is less than every element of the right set. The real number corresponding to a Dedekind cut is defined as the set of all rational numbers that belong to the left set.

The Axiom of Choice and the Law of the Excluded Middle

The axiom of choice and the law of the excluded middle are two fundamental principles in classical mathematics that are often used to prove the existence of certain mathematical objects. The axiom of choice states that for any family of non-empty sets, there exists a choice function that assigns to each set an element from that set. The law of the excluded middle states that for any proposition, either the proposition is true or its negation is true.

In constructive mathematics, these principles are not available, and instead, a more cautious approach is taken. This means that mathematical objects are not assumed to exist unless they can be explicitly constructed.

Constructing a Sequence of Irrational Numbers

Let xRx \in \mathbb{R} be a real number. We want to construct a sequence of irrational numbers that converges to xx. To do this, we need to find a way to approximate xx with increasing precision using irrational numbers.

One possible approach is to use the decimal expansion of xx to construct a sequence of rational numbers that converges to xx. However, this approach is not constructive, as it relies on the law of the excluded middle to prove the existence of the decimal expansion.

A Constructive Approach

A more constructive approach is to use the fact that every real number has a binary expansion. This means that every real number can be written as a sum of powers of 2, where the coefficients are either 0 or 1.

Using this fact, we can construct a sequence of irrational numbers that converges to xx as follows:

  1. Start with an arbitrary irrational number a0a_0.
  2. For each nNn \in \mathbb{N}, define ana_n to be the irrational number that is obtained by adding 2n2^{-n} to an1a_{n-1} if the nn-th digit of the binary expansion of xx is 1, and subtracting 2n2^{-n} from an1a_{n-1} if the nn-th digit of the binary expansion of xx is 0.
  3. The sequence ana_n converges to xx.

The Irrationality of the Sequence

To show that the sequence ana_n is irrational, we need to show that it does not contain any rational numbers. Suppose, for the sake of contradiction, that ana_n is rational for some nn. Then, we can write an=p/qa_n = p/q for some integers pp and qq.

However, this would imply that the nn-th digit of the binary expansion of xx is either 0 or 1, which is a contradiction. Therefore, the sequence ana_n is irrational.

Conclusion

In this article, we have shown that every real number can be constructed as the limit of a sequence of irrational numbers, without using the law of the excluded middle and the axiom of choice. This result is significant, as it provides a constructive proof of the existence of real numbers.

Open Questions

There are several open questions related to this result. For example, it is not clear whether every real number can be constructed as the limit of a sequence of rational numbers. Additionally, it is not clear whether the sequence ana_n can be constructed without using the binary expansion of xx.

Future Work

Future work in this area could involve investigating the properties of the sequence ana_n in more detail. For example, it would be interesting to study the distribution of the digits of the binary expansion of xx in the sequence ana_n.

References

  • [1] Bishop, E., and D. Bridges. Constructive Analysis. Springer-Verlag, 1985.
  • [2] Bridges, D. Constructive Mathematics: A Foundation for Computational Mathematics. Chapman and Hall/CRC, 1999.
  • [3] Myhill, J. "Some Properties of Intuitionistic Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory." In Logic Colloquium '73, edited by H. E. Rose and J. C. Shepherdson, 97-106. North-Holland, 1975.

Appendix

The following is a proof of the fact that every real number has a binary expansion.

Theorem

Every real number has a binary expansion.

Proof

Let xRx \in \mathbb{R} be a real number. We want to show that xx has a binary expansion.

Since xx is a real number, it can be written as a Dedekind cut. Let LL be the left set of the Dedekind cut corresponding to xx.

We can define a function f:NNf: \mathbb{N} \to \mathbb{N} by setting f(n)=min{kN:kL and k>2n}f(n) = \min \{k \in \mathbb{N}: k \in L \text{ and } k > 2^n\}.

We claim that the sequence f(n)f(n) converges to a real number yRy \in \mathbb{R}. To see this, let yy be the real number corresponding to the Dedekind cut {kN:kL and k>2n for some nN}\{k \in \mathbb{N}: k \in L \text{ and } k > 2^n \text{ for some } n \in \mathbb{N}\}.

Then, for each nNn \in \mathbb{N}, we have f(n)Lf(n) \in L and f(n)>2nf(n) > 2^n. Therefore, the sequence f(n)f(n) converges to yy.

Since yy is a real number, it has a binary expansion. Therefore, xx also has a binary expansion.

QED

Introduction

In our previous article, we explored the question of whether every real number can be constructed as the limit of a sequence of irrational numbers, without using the law of the excluded middle and the axiom of choice. In this article, we will answer some of the most frequently asked questions related to this topic.

Q: What is the significance of this result?

A: This result is significant because it provides a constructive proof of the existence of real numbers. In constructive mathematics, the existence of a mathematical object is not assumed unless it can be explicitly constructed. Therefore, this result shows that real numbers can be constructed without relying on the law of the excluded middle and the axiom of choice.

Q: How does this result relate to the axiom of choice?

A: The axiom of choice is a fundamental principle in classical mathematics that states that for any family of non-empty sets, there exists a choice function that assigns to each set an element from that set. In constructive mathematics, the axiom of choice is not available, and instead, a more cautious approach is taken. This result shows that real numbers can be constructed without relying on the axiom of choice.

Q: Can every real number be constructed as the limit of a sequence of rational numbers?

A: This is an open question in constructive mathematics. While we have shown that every real number can be constructed as the limit of a sequence of irrational numbers, it is not clear whether every real number can be constructed as the limit of a sequence of rational numbers.

Q: How does this result relate to the binary expansion of real numbers?

A: The binary expansion of a real number is a way of representing the number as a sum of powers of 2, where the coefficients are either 0 or 1. This result shows that every real number has a binary expansion, which is a fundamental property of real numbers.

Q: Can this result be generalized to other mathematical structures?

A: This result is specific to the real numbers and does not generalize to other mathematical structures. However, it is possible that similar results could be obtained for other mathematical structures, such as the complex numbers or the quaternions.

Q: What are the implications of this result for constructive mathematics?

A: This result has significant implications for constructive mathematics, as it provides a constructive proof of the existence of real numbers. This result shows that constructive mathematics is a viable alternative to classical mathematics, and that it can be used to prove the existence of mathematical objects in a constructive way.

Q: Can this result be used to prove other mathematical theorems?

A: This result can be used to prove other mathematical theorems, such as the intermediate value theorem or the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem. However, the specific implications of this result for other mathematical theorems are still an open question.

Q: What are the limitations of this result?

A: This result has several limitations. For example, it only applies to real numbers and does not generalize to other mathematical structures. Additionally, it relies on the binary expansion of real numbers, which is a fundamental property of real numbers.

Q: Can this result be used to prove the existence of other mathematical objects?

A: This result can be used to prove the existence of other mathematical objects, such as the real numbers themselves. However, the specific implications of this result for other mathematical objects are still an open question.

Conclusion

In this article, we have answered some of the most frequently asked questions related to the question of whether every real number can be constructed as the limit of a sequence of irrational numbers, without using the law of the excluded middle and the axiom of choice. We hope that this article has provided a useful overview of this topic and has helped to clarify some of the key issues involved.

References

  • [1] Bishop, E., and D. Bridges. Constructive Analysis. Springer-Verlag, 1985.
  • [2] Bridges, D. Constructive Mathematics: A Foundation for Computational Mathematics. Chapman and Hall/CRC, 1999.
  • [3] Myhill, J. "Some Properties of Intuitionistic Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory." In Logic Colloquium '73, edited by H. E. Rose and J. C. Shepherdson, 97-106. North-Holland, 1975.

Appendix

The following is a proof of the fact that every real number has a binary expansion.

Theorem

Every real number has a binary expansion.

Proof

Let xRx \in \mathbb{R} be a real number. We want to show that xx has a binary expansion.

Since xx is a real number, it can be written as a Dedekind cut. Let LL be the left set of the Dedekind cut corresponding to xx.

We can define a function f:NNf: \mathbb{N} \to \mathbb{N} by setting f(n)=min{kN:kL and k>2n}f(n) = \min \{k \in \mathbb{N}: k \in L \text{ and } k > 2^n\}.

We claim that the sequence f(n)f(n) converges to a real number yRy \in \mathbb{R}. To see this, let yy be the real number corresponding to the Dedekind cut {kN:kL and k>2n for some nN}\{k \in \mathbb{N}: k \in L \text{ and } k > 2^n \text{ for some } n \in \mathbb{N}\}.

Then, for each nNn \in \mathbb{N}, we have f(n)Lf(n) \in L and f(n)>2nf(n) > 2^n. Therefore, the sequence f(n)f(n) converges to yy.

Since yy is a real number, it has a binary expansion. Therefore, xx also has a binary expansion.

QED

This completes the proof of the fact that every real number has a binary expansion.